1
ARGUMENT
The University of Michigan Law School (Law School)
respondents pay repeated tribute to the manner in which
the Law School engages in a highly individualized,
holistic review of each file, and gives serious consideration
to all of the ways that applicants might contribute to a
diverse educational environment. Resp. Br. 46. See also
id. at 4, 5, 9, 11, 12, 13, 32, 43, 48. Yet, in their 50-page,
80-footnote brief, respondents mention only once by name
the individual who filed this suit, and then the reference is
a disparaging one. See Resp. Br. 47-48 n.78. One could not
learn from their brief that Ms. Grutters application to
their Law School described, in addition to her academic
achievements, Pet. Br. 2, a 43-year-old mother and business
entrepreneur, someone who had started her own
business ten years earlier and made it successful, someone
who had been a first in many of her professional
achievements, and someone interested in non-traditional
methods of education. See Cir. App. 284-92. These life
experiences would have brought a substantial amount of
genuine diversity to a law school class composed largely of
students (of whatever race or ethnicity) who come to the
school directly from college.
Far from mentioning her diversity characteristics, and
in the face of their repeated claim to consider and value
many subjective non-racial diversity factors, Resp. Br.
11, respondents even dismiss out-of-hand (prior to a trial
on the issue) the prospect that Ms. Grutter could be
admitted to their Law School. They reach that conclusion
solely by reference to the fact that other rejected white
applicants had the same or better grade point averages
and LSAT scores as she. Id. at 47-48 n.78. The Law School
could not be clearer in demonstrating what trivial value it
places on these subjective non-racial diversity factors,
especially in relation to skin color diversity, the only kind
of diversity for which it has a commitment to obtaining a
critical mass. App. 120-21.
2
The interest that respondents ask this Court to
recognize as a compelling justification for departing from
the command of equality contained in the Constitution is
indistinguishable from an interest in simple racial balancing.
It is a racial quota palmed off as an ethereal educational
concept. Resp. Br. 32 n.50. What respondents ask
for is an exception to the nondiscrimination principle for
educators, so that they can decide, with virtually unfettered
discretion, what kind and quantity of racial mix to
assemble in our colleges and universities and what weight
to assign a plus and (by implication) a minus on the
basis of immutable racial characteristics. The Court has
never before approved such a standardless justification for
racial discrimination under the exacting requirements of
strict scrutiny. It should not do so now.
- The Law Schools Use of Racial Preferences in
Student Admissions Violates the Equal Protection
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment,
42 U.S.C. § 2000d (Title VI), and 42 U.S.C.
§ 1981.
- The Law Schools Racial Preferences Are
Not Supported by a Compelling Governmental
Interest.
1. This Court and individual Justices have repeatedly
emphasized that state-sponsored racial preferences
impose real harms and costs on the individuals affected by
them and society at large.1 A departure from the command
___________________
1
See, e.g., Rice v. Cayetano, 528 U.S. 495, 517 (2000) ([T]he use of
racial classifications is corruptive of the whole legal order democratic
elections seek to preserve. The law itself may not become the instrument
for generating the prejudice and hostility all too often directed
against persons whose particular ancestry is disclosed by their ethnic
characteristics and cultural traditions.); id. (One of the principal
reasons race is treated as a forbidden classification is that it demeans
the dignity and worth of a person to be judged by ancestry instead of by
his or her own merit and essential qualities.); Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S.
(Continued on following page)
630, 643 (1993) (racial preferences threaten to stigmatize individuals
by reason of their membership in a racial group and to incite racial
hostility); Metro Broad., Inc. v. FCC, 497 U.S. 547, 637 (1990) (Ken-
nedy, J., dissenting) (criticizing majority for not being candid about the
existence of stigma imposed by racial preferences on both affected
classes, candid about the animosity and discontent they create, and
open about defending a theory that explains why the cost of this stigma
is worth bearing and why it can consist with the Constitution) (citation
omitted).
3
of equality contained in the Equal Protection Clause can
be justified only in an extreme case, and then only when
necessary as a temporary means to accomplish a compel-
ling objective. City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., 488
U.S. 469, 509 (1989) (OConnor, J.); see also id. at 519
(Kennedy, J., concurring in part and concurring in the
judgment) (noting that strict scrutiny . . . forbids the use
even of narrowly drawn racial classifications except as a
last resort); Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S. 630, 644 (1993)
(racial classifications require extraordinary justification).
This high threshold has meant that even many laudable
goals, like remedying the effects of societal discrimination
or providing role models for minority school children,
cannot justify a states use of racial preferences. They
deprive innocent individuals of their personal rights,
guaranteed by the Fourteenth Amendment, to be treated
with equal dignity and respect. Croson, 488 U.S. at 493
(OConnor, J.); Wygant v. Jackson Board of Education, 476
U.S. 267, 280-82 (1986) (plurality opinion).
Yet, nearly fifty years after Brown v. Board of Educa-
tion, 347 U.S. 483 (1954), respondents ask this Court to
endorse the use of racial preferences in higher education
admissions until disparities in educational qualifications
among races caused by our Nations discriminatory past
have been eliminated. Resp. Br. 15. Acceptance of respon-
dents indefinite justification for racial preferences in
higher education, expressly linked as it is to effects rooted
in centuries of racial discrimination, Resp. Br. 33, would
mark a momentous step backwards in this Courts
4
[m]odern equal protection doctrine. Metro Broad., Inc. v.
FCC, 497 U.S. 547, 612 (1990) (OConnor, J., dissenting).
Instead, the Court should tolerate no retreat, Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515 U.S. 200, 227 (1995), from
its precedents by rejecting as insufficient and over expan-
sive a basis for imposing racial preferences that is defined
in time and scope by progress made in ameliorating the
persistent effects of societal discrimination.2 Wygant, 476
U.S. at 276 (plurality opinion).
2. The timeless quality of the Law Schools asserted
interest is matched by its ill-defined and amorphous
nature. For the Law School, it is enough to justify large,
indefinite racial preferences in admissions by positing that
there are some unmeasured educational benefits to be
obtained by assembling in the student body what, in the
Law Schools sole discretion, it considers to be a critical
mass of students from certain specified racial and ethnic
groups. Under its approach, it is not necessary to ascertain
whether the dangers and harms, in the nature of stigma,
racial hostility and division, and perpetuation of stereo-
types, outweigh the asserted educational benefits. It is not
even necessary under the Law Schools mode of analysis to
assess (since it never does) whether the claimed benefits
attributed to the preferences, i.e., that which is over and
above what would be produced by the level of diversity in
the absence of preferences, outweigh their harms and
costs. Quite clearly, to the Law School, a compelling
___________________
2
Tying justification of the Law Schools racial preferences to
educational disparities caused by historical race discrimination
presents intractable problems. For example, it would require some
means of assessing whether, and to what extent, such disparities are
caused by historical race discrimination rather than by other factors so
that the preferences could be narrowly tailored accordingly. The Law
School offers no explanation for how these assessments are to be made
or who is to make them (presumably separately for different groups,
since circumstances may vary among them). Perhaps this is because
respondents are testing the waters with this argument for the first time
in the more than five years that this case has been pending.
5
interest for racial preferences is merely one that it believes
produces some social benefit (whether or not there is a net
gain). That simply does not satisfy the demanding re-
quirements of strict scrutiny.
The educational claims that the Law School makes for
having a critical mass of minority students are no better
defined than the educational claims asserted in defense of
the racial preferences struck down in Wygant. Notwithstanding
respondents denial to the contrary, see Resp. Br.
31 n.48, the Jackson Board of Education in Wygant most
certainly did argue that its racial preferences were justified
in part by the educational benefits of racial diversity
in that case, diversity of the faculty.3 In its brief to this
Court, the Board explained:
The Jackson Board was convinced that the
presence of black teachers would bring an important
perspective to students and faculty, and that
such a diverse faculty would be able to relate
valuable experiences and bring new perceptions
to the classroom that would contribute to the students
total educational experience and add a
needed balance to the faculty curriculum.4
___________________
3
The right of an educational institution to choose who may teach
is one of the four essential freedoms identified by Justice Frankfurter
in his opinion quoted by Justice Powell in Regents of the University of
California v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265, 312 (1978) (Powell, J.) (quoting
Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 U.S. 234, 263 (1957) (Frankfurter, J.,
concurring)).
4 Brief of Respondents in Wygant, 166 LANDMARK BRIEFS AND
ARGUMENTS OF THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES 119-20
(Philip B. Kurland and Gerhard Casper eds. 1987); id. at 118-19 (The
Jackson Board . . . was concerned both with educational values and the
remedial need to integrate.); id. at 119 (The Jackson Board concluded
that white students should be exposed to black teachers and should be
prepared to participate in a multi-racial society.); id. at 120-21 (If a
state university has a compelling interest in admitting a racially
diverse student body, it would seem that a local school board has at
least as compelling an interest in attempting to secure a racially
diverse faculty.) (footnote omitted). Throughout its brief, the Board
(Continued on following page)
relied on Justice Powells articulation in Bakke of the diversity rationale
in defending the legitimacy of the Boards preferences and educational
goals. At oral argument in this Court, counsel for the Board
referred in some form to diversity no fewer than nine times. Oral
Argument of Mr. Jerome A. Susskind, quoted in 166 LANDMARK BRIEFS
636, 637, 638, 640, 643, 645, 646.
6
Both the role model theory articulated in Wygant
and the diversity rationale put forth by respondents here
are predicated on a theory that increased minority representation
(whether in the faculty or student body) produces
educational benefits. See Wygant, 476 U.S. at 315
(Stevens, J., dissenting) (noting that purpose of seeking
multi-ethnic representation on the teaching faculty was
completely sound educational purpose). There is no
logical stopping point, Wygant, 476 U.S. at 275 (plurality
opinion), for either of these educational justifications for
racial preferences, as they are not measured with respect
to the accomplishment of any identified remedial purpose
and could be used to justify race-based decisionmaking
essentially limitless in scope and duration. Croson, 488
U.S. at 498 (quoting Wygant, 476 U.S. at 276 (plurality
opinion)). There will always be some racial or ethnic group
that is underrepresented to an extent that it does not
have a critical mass, so that there will be a need for the
kind of year-to-year calibration, in effect, racial balancing,
that is also inherent in the rejected role model theory.
Wygant, 476 U.S. at 275 (plurality opinion). Hence, the
conclusion that the Law Schools asserted interest in racial
diversity (i.e., critical mass) is not capable of being the
most compelling of reasons that it must be to survive strict
scrutiny is fully supported by the compelling-interest
analysis contained in the Courts precedents, including
Croson and Wygant.
3. The same conclusion can be derived from the way
in which the Law Schools stated interest in diversity is
premised on stereotypes and the use of race as a proxy for
viewpoint, notions that the Court and individual Justices
7
have rightly condemned as antithetical to the principle of
equality. Respondents vacillate back and forth between
arguing, on the one hand, that mere racial status is
enough to assure that a particular minority will have
viewpoints and perspectives of a kind particularly valu-
able to the Law School, see, e.g., Resp. Br. 24-25; App. 120
(Law School policy statement that members of the hist-
orically discriminated against racial groups are consid-
ered to have experiences and perspectives of special
importance to the Law Schools mission), and on the other
hand, acknowledging as a fiction that race determines a
persons belief and behavior. Resp. Br. 30 (footnote
omitted) (citing Metro Broad., 497 U.S. at 618 (OConnor,
J., dissenting)).
These two rationales are at war with one another. If
race does not determine belief and behavior, it makes no
sense to assume, based on nothing other than racial
status, that a member of a particular minority group will
have experiences or perspectives (beliefs) of special
importance to a schools mission. Moreover, neither of
these rationales can be a legitimate foundation for respon-
dents racial preferences. Drawing racial classifications on
the premise that minority status can be equated with
viewpoint is undisputedly an impermissible basis for
drawing racial classifications. See, e.g., Miller v. Johnson,
515 U.S. 900, 914 (1995). Yet, if the Law School genuinely
recognizes that race does not determine[ ] a persons
belief and behavior, Resp. Br. 30, then the logic of its
justification for granting a racial preference as a means of
getting viewpoint diversity collapses entirely.
It is no defense to respondents asserted use of race as
a proxy for viewpoint that they abjure the notion that
there is some characteristic minority viewpoint on any
issue. Id. The same point was made with respect to the
FCCs use of racial preferences in the award of broadcast
licenses to increase diversity of minority viewpoints in
Metro Broadcasting. 497 U.S. at 582 ([W]e are under no
illusion that members of a particular minority group share
some cohesive, collective viewpoint.); id. at 579 (The
predictive judgment about the overall result of minority
8
entry into broadcasting is not a rigid assumption about
how minority owners will behave in every case. . . .).
Respondents argument here is essentially that use of race
as a proxy for viewpoint will somehow in the aggregate,
result in greater [viewpoint] diversity. Id. at 579. This
reasoning reveals the extent to which respondents as-
serted interest is not compatible with the demands of
strict scrutiny. Id. at 620 (OConnor, J., dissenting) (This
reliance on the aggregate and on probabilities confirms
that the Court has abandoned heightened scrutiny, which
requires a direct rather than approximate fit of means to
ends.).
There are other pernicious stereotypes that underlie
respondents use of race as a proxy allegedly to promote
viewpoint diversity. One is the assumption that the ex-
periences of particular racial groups are of such impor-
tance and relevance that they justify granting preferences
in admissions to members of these groups. The corollary
to this notion is plain: Individuals of unfavored racial and
ethnic backgrounds are unlikely to possess the unique
experiences and background that contribute to viewpoint
diversity. Id. at 619. A second stereotype is found in
respondents assumption that many or most white stu-
dents believe that all minorities think alike. See Amicus
Curiae Brief of Law Professors Larry Alexander, et al. 14.
Even if these questionable and unattractive propositions
have some empirical basis, equal protection principles
prohibit respondents from relying on them to justify their
racial preferences. Metro Broad., 497 U.S. at 620
(OConnor, J., dissenting).
4. In arguing that a majority in Regents of the
University of California v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265 (1978),
endorsed the Law Schools diversity rationale, respondents
have instead cobbled together their own separate rationale
that none of the Justices in Bakke endorsed. They do so by
linking and limiting the legitimacy of the diversity interest
to remedial purposes the use of race must cease under
a policy like the Harvard plan when the disparities in
applicants numerical qualifications produced by our
Nations discriminatory past have been eliminated. Resp.
9
Br. 15. Nowhere in his opinion did Justice Powell define the
diversity interest in such terms or limit it to any remedial
context, and he expressly repudiated the effects of societal
discrimination as a basis for justifying preferences. Bakke,
438 U.S. at 307 (Powell, J.). Similarly, it requires resort to
speculation and a re-write of Justice Brennans opinion to
conclude that what he mean[t] by the lingering effects of
societal discrimination was disparities in applicants
numerical qualifications. Resp. Br. 15.
Respondents argument that there is a limitation on
the diversity rationale that is contained only in Justice
Brennans opinion is also inconsistent with their argument
that Justice Powells opinion is the narrower one under
the analysis approved in Marks v. United States, 430 U.S.
188 (1977). In effect, respondents are now arguing that it
is Justice Brennans opinion, with its remedial rationale,
that is controlling. Indeed, Justice Powells nonremedial
articulation of the diversity rationale becomes superfluous
under respondents reasoning, which has it that in the
absence of the effects of lingering discrimination, racial
diversity could be achieved without resort to racial prefer-
ences. Resp. Br. at 15-16 (noting that a racially diverse
class could then be assembled by other means, i.e.,
without considering race). The absurd result produced by
respondents contortionist interpretation of the opinions is
that Justice Brennans opinion, which mentions no inter-
est in diversity,5 marks the limits of that interest in
remedial terms, even though Justice Powell, who alone in
Bakke articulated the diversity rationale, in no way
confined it to the remedial context.
___________________
5
Justice Brennans brief references to the Harvard plan were in a
context that limited any endorsement of the use of race in such a plan to
circumstances justified by past discrimination and a showing of disadvan-
tage on the part of a minority applicant, Bakke, 438 U.S. at 316 (Brennan,
J.), limits which are absent from the Law Schools admissions program.
Thus, whatever the Harvard plan (which, of course, was not before the
Court in Bakke) may have been in reality, Justice Brennan and those
Justices who joined his opinion viewed it as a remedial plan.
10
Ultimately, both sides can cite to law review commen-
tary and court cases for their opposing positions on what
meaning emerged from various opinions in Bakke. 6 Given
the fractured nature of those opinions, as noted by all the
Justices of this Court, see Pet. 28, and the sharp division
among the lower courts, id., it is hard to fathom how
respondents can genuinely persist in contending that their
view represents either obvious or settled law.7 Resp. Br.
16-17.
5. In the end, the Law Schools assertion of a compelling
interest boils down to its incendiary canard that the
Law School and others like it will become resegregated if
they must discontinue their use of racial preferences in
admissions. Resp. Br. 13, 19-20. By resegregation,
respondents do not mean that minorities will be intention-
ally excluded. Rather, the provocative term is used to
indicate that these schools will admit fewer students from
the currently-favored minority groups than is the case
under the current race-based regime. Even then, respon-
dents have painted a false or wildly exaggerated picture.
This can be seen in empirical evidence from the admis-
sions offices of selective law schools that have for several
years operated under a rule foreclosing use of racial
preferences in admissions. This years first-year class at
Boalt Hall School of Law, which by common repute is as
___________________
6
The Law School contends that it was immediately obvious after
Bakke that Justice Powells diversity analysis was controlling. Resp. Br.
16-17. In fact, a number of courts either explicitly rejected this conclu-
sion, expressed doubt about it, or read Justice Brennans four-Justice
plurality opinion as containing the controlling rationale. See, e.g.,
Britton v. South Bend Comm. Sch., 775 F.2d 794, 803 n.12, 809 (7th Cir.
1985); Valentine v. Smith, 654 F.2d 503, 509 & n.9 (8th Cir. 1981);
United States v. City of Miami, 614 F.2d 1322, 1337-38 (5th Cir. 1980).
7 For additional arguments addressing respondents erroneous
contention that principles of stare decisis furnish a reason to accept
Justice Powells articulation of the diversity rationale in Bakke as
binding or settled, see Petioners Reply Brief 7-10, in Gratz v. Bollin
ger (No. 02-516).
11
selective as respondents Law School, has 19.9% represen-
tation from the underrepresented (African American,
Hispanic, Native American) groups, a percentage substan-
tially exceeding the critical mass that respondents
typically ensure through use of their preferences.8 For the
last several years, Boalts enrollments from these racial
groups have been comparable to the enrollments at re-
spondents school, and there is no indication that it em-
ploys any percent plan or has significantly diminished its
commitment to academic selectivity. A similar situation
exists at the law schools at the University of California at
Davis,9 UCLA,10 and the University of Texas.11 The num-
bers belie respondents casual prophecies about resegre-
gation and assertion that race-neutral alternatives are
unavailable for highly selective professional schools.12
___________________
8
See http://www.ucop.edu/acadadv/datamgmt/lawdata/lawschl3.html.
The first-year enrollments at Boalt from the underrepresented groups
totaled 10.7% in 2001, 9.7% in 2000, 9.2% in 1999, and 12.3% in 1998.
Id.
9 16.3% in 2002; 8.9% in 2001; 8.9% in 2000, 12.4% in 1999, and
9.3% in 1998. See http://www.ucop.edu/acadadv/datamgmt/lawschl3.
html.
10 12.9% in 2002; 12.9% in 2001; 12.1% in 2000; 7.5% in 1999; and
9.8% in 1998. Id.
11 14.2% in 2002; 12.8% in 2001; 12% in 2000; 10.1% in 1999; and
12.5% in 1998. See http://www.utexas.edu/academic/oir/statistical_hand
book/02-03/students/s04b/. The trial court record also includes evidence
on the admissions data from California and Texas schools available as
of that date. Cir. App. 5123, 5125, 5127, 5129.
12 Rather than basing their predictions on real world experience,
respondents rely on their own self-serving computer models, which
make assumptions far beyond removing the use of race in the admis-
sions process. These assumptions are that in a race-neutral admissions
system, the Law School will consider only test scores and grades, that it
will admit students strictly in rank order of these credentials, and that
other schools will continue to use racial preferences. Resp. Br. 6 & n.7.
Such a system would be completely different from the one they claim to
operate now, in which each file receives highly individualized, holistic,
id. at 46, review and in which many subjective, non-racial diversity
factors are considered. Id. at 11. Moreover, even under respondents
(Continued on following page)
modeled worst-case scenario, there would still be representation from
the underrepresented groups in the class, so that it is inaccurate to
describe the result as resegregation. Accordingly, the interest that
respondents defend here is not one of integration, Resp. Br. 1, 14, 22,
because the Law School will certainly remain integrated after its
preferences are found unlawful. Rather, the interest that respondents
seek to elevate to the status of compelling is one in racial balancing,
Croson, 488 U.S. at 507, which is simply discrimination for its own
sake. Bakke, 438 U.S. at 307 (Powell, J.).
12
6. To the extent the intervenor respondents make
substantive arguments13 different from the Law School
respondents, they are undisguised appeals to justify the
Law Schools preferences on grounds of societal discrimi-
nation. Their contention is not that there is a history of
any identified, purposeful discrimination in admissions by
the Law School against the minority groups that receive a
preference. Rather, it is that an admissions system that
relies on criteria of grades and test scores is biased against
minorities.
First, contrary to intervenors misstatement, Resp.
Interv. Br. 38 (plaintiff embraced test scores and grades),
it is not petitioner who insists that the Law School use any
particular admissions criteria. It is the Law School that
has chosen, as it explains at length in defining academic
selectivity, to rely heavily on these numerical qualifica-
tions.14 Resp. Br. 5-6. Second, intervenors do not argue
___________________
13
Intervenors direct numerous ad hominem attacks at petitioner,
her counsel, and statistical expert. The brief is also replete with
misleading statements or assertions made without benefit of citation.
Thus, for example, intervenors falsely state that the district court
conceded that the elimination of affirmative action at the Law School
would result in an immediate reduction in underrepresented minority
enrollment of over 73 percent. [Pet. App.] 223a. Resp. Interv. Br. 6. In
fact, at the point referenced by intervenors, the district court merely
recited the testimony of a Law School witness, only to subsequently
reject it. Pet. App. 228a. See also Resp. Interv. Br. 36 (asserting that
Florida established two new state law schools [in 2000] one for black
students and one for Latinos).
14 To the extent that the intervenor respondents rely on defenses of
the Law Schools racial preferences that did not actually motivate the
(Continued on following page)
Law School to adopt them, these defenses are legally insufficient to
justify them. See, e.g., Shaw v. Hunt, 517 U.S. 899, 908 n.4 (1996);
United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515, 535-36 (1996).
13
that the numerical criteria fail to predict, for minorities as
well as others, what they are designed to predict: first-
year grades.15 Third, if these indicators are biased and are
not educationally justified, then they should be eliminated,
not race-normed. Intervenors cite no case for the proposi-
tion that criteria shown to be biased should be used
anyway in conjunction with a preference to offset the bias.
Indeed, the courts that have addressed this argument
have appropriately rejected it. See Aiken v. City of Memp-
his, 37 F.3d 1155, 1164 (6th Cir. 1994) (en banc) (citing
Billish v. City of Chicago, 989 F.2d 890, 894 (7th Cir. 1993)
(en banc)); Ensley Branch, N.A.A.C.P. v. Seibels, 31 F.3d
1548, 1572 (11th Cir. 1994).
- The Law Schools Racial Preferences Are
Not Narrowly Tailored.
1. Respondents conception of ensuring enrollment of
a critical mass of students from the preferred racial and
ethnic groups is not functionally different from the formal
quota employed by Davis in Bakke. Just as the seats set
aside by Davis were available only to members of specified
races (albeit only disadvantaged individuals), only mem-
bers of certain racial or ethnic groups can contribute to the
critical mass that respondents policies are designed to
attain. Barbara Grutter, solely because of her race, is
ineligible to be considered for a space in the class based on
contribution to critical mass. The concept describes a
category reserved exclusively for certain minority
groups, Croson, 488 U.S. at 496 (OConnor, J.), and from
___________________
15
The evidence in the record is that they are valid predictors for
this purpose. Cir. App. 7500-02. See Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229,
250 (1976) (test for entry into police training program could be corre-
lated with success in the training program rather than success as a
police officer).
14
which members of other racial groups are totally ex-
cluded. Bakke, 438 U.S. at 319 (Powell, J.).
It is also undisputed that mass means numbers and
that critical means numbers sufficient in respondents
judgment. Attainment of the objective of critical mass is
hence measured in the same manner one would measure
whether a quota has been filled with reference to
whether the numbers achieved fall above or below the
desired objective. Given that the concept of critical mass
as defined by respondents is inherently tied to a focus on
producing sufficient numbers (meaningful numbers,
Resp. Br. 4) of the preferred minority students, it is hard
to understand how respondents can protest when it is
simply pointed out that the actual admissions data con-
firm the consistent accomplishment of the numerical
objective.
It is not tenable to suggest that there should be a
constitutionally significant distinction between a system
that sets aside a fixed number of spaces in the class and
one that is designed to ensure that some approximate
range of spaces are to be filled by a racially defined criti-
cal mass. The distinction that respondents try to make
between quotas and goals is beside the point because it
is disingenuous for them to suggest that their concept of
critical mass merely represents aspirational goals or a
hope. Resp. Br. 38-39, 42. The Law Schools policy man-
dates enrollment of a critical mass of students from the
preferred minority groups, and its admissions officers
understand that they are required to comply with the
policy, as they do each year.16 The respondents disagree-
ment about whether there is in fact a numerical range
that represents critical mass is a disagreement with the
___________________
16
The policy describes a commitment to ensuring enrollment of
a critical mass each year. App. 120-21. Respondents admissions
director testified that she considered this to be a mandate. Cir. App.
7250.
15
district courts findings, which are supported by the
testimony of the Law Schools witnesses, documents, and
admissions data,17 and are certainly not clearly erroneous.
2. While critical mass describes the result that the
Law School seeks to achieve with its preferences, it is
necessary to examine the size of the preference to under-
stand how respondents achieve their desired objective. In
Bakke, the racial objective was attained through a sepa-
rate minority admissions committee that decided who
received one of the 16 reserved places in the class. In this
case, respondents instead use separate admissions stan-
dards to accomplish their objective.
It is no exaggeration to describe the size of the Law
Schools plus for race as staggering or to conclude that
the data reveal shocking comparisons of admissions
outcomes in many cases. Pet. App. 133a (Boggs, J., dis-
senting). On the criteria that the Law School admits are
important (and that define for them academic selectiv-
ity), comparably qualified students from different racial
groups have such systematically different admission
probabilities that there can be no denying the existence of
a two-track system. It defies understanding how respon-
dents can call these differences modest, especially in
those frequent cases when admission rates for members of
the favored minority groups are 80% to 100%, compared to
20% and lower for members of other groups with the same
or similar numerical credentials. See, e.g., App. 156-203;
Pet. App. 312a-319a. Respondents lack of candor on this
point is also shown in their willingness to argue two
___________________
17
See Pet. Br. 4-10. Respondents contend that variations in the
admissions data across years are inconsistent with the notion that
critical mass constitutes the functional equivalent of a quota. As
Judge Boggs noted in his dissent, some variation in enrollment
numbers is to be anticipated since respondents do not have complete
control over yield. Pet. App. 142a n.29.
16
contradictory notions that race is only a modest consid-
eration in its system and that removal of just that one
factor will cause resegregation. Resp. Br. 43-44.
Respondents ultimately, however, all but concede that
they operate a race-based two-track system by describing
their dual objectives of academic selectivity and racial
diversity. Id. at 1. At this point, they even abandon the
pretense of identifying their diversity interest in terms of
intellectual or experiential diversity. They make clear that
applying to the preferred minority students the same
standard on numerical qualifications under which 90% of
white students are admitted would prevent respondents
from achieving their racially-defined critical mass. Id. at
5. This could not be a clearer acknowledgment of the two-
track nature of the admissions standard.
3. Respondents use of race in its system is not
remotely like the individualized, case-by-case considera-
tion that Justice Powell spoke of approvingly as part of an
effort to obtain an intellectually diverse class. Bakke, 438
U.S. at 319 n.53 (Powell, J.). While respondents suggest
that the extent to which race matters may vary depending
on individual circumstances, see Resp. Br. 37, the policy
which they defend is premised on an a priori judgment
that the racial status of the groups they prefer equates
with experiences and perspectives on which the Law
School places a special importance. There is no reason to
conclude that the Law School could not consider a particu-
lar applicants personal experiences, on an individualized
basis, even experiences that are associated with race. But
respondents approach is one in which race is simply used
as a proxy for experiential diversity.18 Because respondents
consider the mere experience of being a member of one of
the preferred racial groups a valuable contribution to
___________________
18
Respondents practically concede as much; it is just that they
consider race to be a very good proxy, if not perfect. Resp. Br. 30.
17
educational diversity, the dissenters had it just right in
describing the system as one in which race is a proxy for
race. Pet. App. 121a (Boggs, J., dissenting).
By treating Justice Powells statement that the
weight attributable to a particular quality may vary from
year to year, Bakke, 438 U.S. at 317-18 (Powell, J.), as a
license to treat race as a special category, respondents
demonstrate that their real interest is racial balancing. No
other type of diversity in respondents system is identified as
having importance sufficient to require a critical mass.19
While members of the racial groups preferred by the Law
School are presumed to have experiences and perspectives
worthy of a preference, members of other racial groups are
considered to be part of a homogeneous (and over-
represented) mass. App. 122a (Boggs, J., dissenting).
4. Respondents offer empty solace in the assurance
that their use of racial preferences imposes on those
groups that do not receive a preference a small and
diffuse burden which barely affects their chances at
all. Resp. Br. 47. The same was true in Bakke, where
invalidating the system opened up only 16 seats for the
more than two or three thousand applicants from the
disfavored groups. Bakke, 438 U.S. at 273 n.2, 275 n.5
(Powell, J.). According to the Law School, those students
denied admission because of their race can attend school
elsewhere. Resp. Br. 48. But see Metro Broad., 497 U.S. at
630 (OConnor, J., dissenting) (It is no response to a
person denied admission at one school, or discharged from
one job, solely on the basis of race, that other schools or
employers do not discriminate.). Of course, the same
could be said of those individuals from the preferred
minority races who would not receive offers of admission
from respondents in a nondiscriminatory admissions
system. Respondents argument is just one more instance
___________________
19
Moreover, the Law School certainly does not track other kinds of
diversity on a daily basis in the admissions season, like it does for racial
diversity.
18
of how their conception of our Constitution is one that
protects the right of racial groups, not individuals.
5. Finally, as the district court found, there is no
time limit on respondents use of preferences. Pet. App.
247a. Their suggestion that the preferences will come to
an end some day merely confirms that the planned dura-
tion is indefinite, as would be any time limit defined, as
respondents now define it, with reference to the lingering
effects of societal discrimination. Resp. Br. 31.
- C. The Law Schools Racial Preferences Vio-
late 42 U.S.C. § 1981.
Respondents assert without elaboration that peti-
tioner did not preserve an argument that she is entitled to
prevail under 42 U.S.C. § 1981. See Resp. Br. 1 n.1. Peti-
tioner raised the claim in the district court20 and never
argued below that Section 1981 prohibited only the same
conduct prohibited by the Equal Protection Clause, so
there is nothing new about the contention that the terms
of the statute prohibit conduct that the Equal Protection
Clause does not. Moreover, the fact that the Court has
held that Section 1981 reaches only purposeful conduct,
General Bldg. Contractors Assn v. Pennsylvania, 458 U.S.
375, 389-90 (1982), does not mean that the statute reaches
only the same purposeful conduct prohibited by the Four-
teenth Amendment. Section 1981 remains an independent
basis on which to reverse the judgment of the court of
appeals.
___________________
20
See Plaintiffs Memorandum of Law in Support of Motion for
Summary Judgment on Liability 37-38, filed May 3, 1999 (district court
Record No. 94).
19
- II. The Court of Appeals Should Have Reviewed
and Affirmed the District Courts Findings
Under the Clearly Erroneous Standard of
Review and Should Not Have Reviewed the
Findings De Novo.
The Law School seemingly has read right out of the
case the second question presented in the petition that
this Court granted whether the court of appeals erred in
reviewing the district courts findings after a trial under a
de novo, rather than the clearly erroneous, standard of
review.21 The Law School elides the point by contending
that there is no genuine dispute in this case about the
historical facts, Resp. Br. 1, but then it proceeds to dis-
pute facts actually found by the district court.
For example, respondents dispute the district courts
finding that the Law School effectively reserves seats for
members of the favored minority groups.22 Pet. App. 249a;
Resp. Br. 41 n.9. They do so also with respect to the
district courts findings on the identity of the racial and
ethnic groups included within the preferences. Pet. App.
249a; Resp. Br. 49 n.79. In the latter case, respondents
falsely imply that the dispute is with petitioner only, and
not with the district court. Resp. Br. 49 n.79. They persist
in suggesting that petitioner and her statistical expert
created the racial and ethnic categories into which the
evidence on admissions data is organized, when it is the
___________________
21
Neither of respondents merits briefs identify anywhere the
second question presented for review.
22 Respondents assert that the district courts finding that the Law
School has effectively reserved approximately 10% of the seats in each
entering class for the preferred minorities, Pet. App. 249a, is inconsis-
tent with its finding that there are no fixed number of seats reserved.
Resp. Br. 8, 40. This is disingenuous, as in the same sentence quoted by
respondents, the district court noted that there is no principled
difference between a fixed number of seats and an essentially fixed
minimum percentage figure. Pet. App. 248a.
20
Law School that not only maintains these categories, but
also keeps daily track of decisions on admissions and
acceptances for each group.23 Finally, respondents asser-
tion that the Law School has studied th[e] issue of [race-
neutral alternatives] for many years, Resp. Br. 33-34, is
another contradiction of the district courts findings. See
Pet. App. 251a. The mere fact that some of respondents
witnesses testified during trial that they did not believe
race-neutral alternatives were feasible is not at all incon-
sistent with the district courts finding that respondents
had not considered such alternatives prior to implement-
ing their preferences.
In arguing with the findings of the district court,
respondents implicitly acknowledge that those findings
are incompatible with a conclusion that respondents racial
preferences are lawful. By failing to directly address the
second question presented in the petition, it is reasonable
to conclude that respondents have effectively conceded
that the court of appeals erred in application of a de novo
standard of review.
CONCLUSION
For all the foregoing reasons, petitioner respectfully
requests this Court to reverse the judgment of the court of
appeals.
___________________
23
Respondents newly contend, with no citation to the record, that
the categories it maintains are only for compliance with legal require-
ments and ABA standards. Resp. Br. 43 n.70. This hardly explains the
need to track data daily; it also contradicts the testimony of respon-
dents admissions director, who made clear that the daily tracking is
used to help the Law School get its critical mass, Cir. App. 7334; and
more importantly, it is another instance of respondents taking issue
with a factual finding of the district court, see Pet. App. 230a, without
explaining how the finding is clearly erroneous.
|
Respectfully submitted,
|
MICHAEL E. ROSMAN
HANS BADER
CENTER FOR INDIVIDUAL
RIGHTS
Suite 300
1233 20th Street N.W.
Washington, D.C. 20036
(202) 833-8400
KERRY L. MORGAN
PENTIUK, COUVREUR &
KOBILJAK, P.C.
2915 Biddle Avenue
Edelson Building
Suite 200
Wyandotte, MI 48192
(734) 281-7100
|
KIRK O. KOLBO
Counsel of Record
DAVID F. HERR
R. LAWRENCE PURDY
MICHAEL C. MCCARTHY
KAI H. RICHTER
MASLON EDELMAN BORMAN
& BRAND, LLP
3300 Wells Fargo Center
90 South Seventh Street
Minneapolis, MN 55402
(612) 672-8200
|
|